Is science only about finding things out? Or are there problems or puzzles that we are trying to solve? How often do we stop to wonder at what sort of enterprise we are engaged in? We imbibe how to do science over a long period of time beginning at school and going on to various levels at university. After university, it may take other particularly practical forms. If we are involved in a problem or puzzle solving version of science, exactly what is it that we are trying to solve? Engrossed in the practical elements of research, we may sometimes overlook our precise goals.
Consider the puzzles in newspapers or magazines or those in the apps on our smartphones. Some people naturally gravitate towards number puzzles, some to word puzzles others to more strategic puzzles like chess. The variety of considerable. As a species we are ‘solvers’. It is is sometimes suggested that our inquisitiveness is what gave rise to science. I suggest that our desire to ‘solve’ played a large part too.
I have used the words ‘problem’ and ‘puzzle’. In philosophy there is a distinction to be made between them. Problems are substantive by nature and, as a result, carry a certain importance. Puzzles are primarily linguistic by nature and rely on how words are used. (This is further complicated by the fact that a word’s meaning may shift over time.)
Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951) claimed that in philosophy there were only linguistic puzzles. Sir Karl Popper (1902-1994) did not hold that opinion. Popper was asked to address the matter in a paper entitled "Are There Philosophical Problems?" at a meeting of the Cambridge University Moral Sciences Club on 25 October 1946.
At that meeting, he appears to have applied thinking akin to that characteristic of that for which many scientists know him. It may be expressed as follows:
- The question "Are There Philosophical Problems?" is itself a philosophical problem (it is clearly not a linguistic puzzle).
- Thus, there is at least one philosophical problem.
- Therefore, philosophy does not consist of linguistic puzzles alone.
This is a key theme in Edmonds and Eidinow’s book ‘Wittgenstein’s Poker’ first published in 2001 (and which I can highly recommend reading).
Some puzzles are solved by putting the pieces together. A jigsaw puzzle is an obvious example. All the king’s horses and all the king’s men set out to do something akin to a jigsaw puzzle when trying to put Humpty together again. Since it did not work, that approach was clearly the wrong one. Reconstructing Humpty is problem not a puzzle.
When trying to understand the human body scientifically, we are engaged in a process of taking the body apart and then not even trying to put the pieces together again. This deconstruction is, of course, done conceptually. Even if we were allowed, we could not take a living organism apart and it put it back together again alive. An organ may be surgically exposed and experimented upon. It is technically possible to remove an organ from the body and return it at another time. But we cannot expect to do this to several organs at once.
If we are going to deconstruct the body conceptually, we must find a way to reconstruct it conceptually, too. One way of doing this may be to move away from simply seeing organs as separate components of specific physiological systems and looking at how they work together with others organs - not least those in other systems.
A simple example is that of the heart and lungs and the way in which they work together. Typically they are addressed quite separately: the heart is described as part of the cardiovascular system and the lungs as part of the respiratory system. A textbook may describe them many pages apart and yet anatomically they are side-by-side and physiologically they have complementary roles with regard to respiratory gas transport. A conceptual linkage of the two is already done by teacher and student in and out of the classroom. There are other possibilities and there is scope for a more formal recognition of this type of thinking by textbooks.